Theory : Ernest Mandel Archive : The Leninist Theory of
Organisation
Marxism
Bourgeois ideology and proletarian class consciousness
Leninist Organisation - Part 2
Ernest Mandel
[...]
The formation of the working class as an objective category is
itself an historical process. Some sections of the working class are the sons,
grandsons, and great-grandsons of urban wage labourers; others are the sons and
grandsons of agricultural labourers and landless peasants, Still others are
only first or second generation descendants of a petty bourgeoisie that owned
some means of production (peasants, artisans, etc.). Part of the working class
works in large factories where both the economic and the social relations give
rise to at least an elementary class consciousness (consciousness that
"social questions" can be solved only through collective activity and
organisation). Another part works in small or medium-sized factories in
industry or in the so-called service sectors, where economic self-confidence as
well as an understanding of the necessity for broad mass actions flow much less
easily from the objective situation than in the large industrial plant. Some
sections of the working class have been living in big cities for a long time.
They have been literate for a long time and have several generations of
trade-union organisation and political and cultural education behind them
(through youth organisations, the workers press, labour education, etc.). Still
others live in small towns or even in the countryside. (This was true into the
late 1930s, for instance, for a significant number of European miners.) These
workers have little or no collective social life, scarcely any trade-union
experience, and have received no political or cultural education at all in the
organised workers movement. Some sectors of the working class are born from
nations which were independent for a thousand years, and whose ruling class
oppressed for long periods other nations. Other workers are born from nations
which fought for decades or centuries for their national freedom - or who lived
in slavery or serfdom no more than one hundred years ago. If one adds to all
these historical and structural differences the various personal abilities of
each wage worker - not just differences in intelligence and ability to
generalise from immediate experiences, but differences in the amount of energy,
strength of character: combatively and self-assurance too - then one
understands that the stratification of the working class into various layers,
depending on the degree of class consciousness, is an inevitable phenomenon in
the history of the working class itself. It is this historical process of
becoming a class which, at a given point in time, is reflected in the various
degrees of consciousness within the class.
The category of the revolutionary party stems from the fact that
Marxian socialism is a science which, in the final analysis, can be completely
assimilated only in an individual and not in a collective manner. Marxism
constitutes the culmination (and in part also the dissolution) of at least
three classical social sciences: classical German philosophy, classical
political economy, and classical French political science (French socialism and
historiography). Its assimilation presupposes at least an understanding of the
materialist dialectic, historical materialism, Marxian economic theory and the
critical history of modern revolutions and of the modern labour movement. Such
an assimilation is necessary if it is to be able to function, in its totality,
as an instrument for analysing social reality and as the compilation of the experiences
of a century of proletarian class struggle. The notion that this colossal sum
of knowledge and information could somehow spontaneously flow from working at a
lathe or a calculating machine is absurd. [[To counter this view, many critics
of the Leninist concept of organisation (beginning with Plekhanov’s article,
"Centralism or Bonapartism" in Iskra, No, 70 [Summer, 1904]),
refer to a passage in The Holy Family - The passage states: "When
socialist writers ascribe this historic role to the proletariat, it is not, as
Critical Criticism pretends to think, because they consider the proletarians as
gods. Rather the contrary. Since the abstraction of all humanity, even
of the semblance of humanity, is practically complete in the full-grown
proletariat; since the conditions of life of the proletariat sum up all the
conditions of life of society today in all their inhuman acuity; since man has
lost himself in the proletariat, yet at the same time has not only gained
theoretical consciousness of that loss, but through urgent, no longer
disguisable, absolutely imperative need - that practical expression of necessity
- is driven to revolt against that inhumanity; it follows that the proletariat
can and must free itself. But it cannot free itself without abolishing the
conditions of its own life. It cannot abolish the conditions of its own life
without abolishing all the inhuman conditions of life of society today
which are summed up in its own situation. Not in vain does it go through the
stern but steeling school of labour. The question is not what this or
that proletarian, or even the whole of the proletariat, at the moment considers
as its aim. The question is what the proletariat is and what, consequent
on that being, it will be compelled to do. Its aim and historical action
is irrevocably and obviously demonstrated in its own life situation as well as
in the whole organisation of burgeons society today. There is no need to dwell
here upon the fact that a large part of the English and French proletariat is already
conscious of its historic task and is constantly working to develop that
consciousness into complete clarity." Karl Marx and Frederick Engels: The
Holy Family (Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1956). pp.52-53.
Aside from the fact that Marx and Engels were hardly in a position
in 1844-1845 to produce a mature theory of proletarian class consciousness and
proletarian organisation (to become aware of this, one need only compare the
last sentence of the above quotation with what Engels wrote forty years later
about the English working class), these lines say the very opposite of what
Plekhanov reads into them. They say only that the social situation of
the proletariat prepares it for radical, revolutionary action, and that the
determination of the general socialist objective (the abolition of private
property) is "pre scribed" by its conditions of life. In no way do
they indicate, however, that the proletariat’s "inhuman conditions of
life" will somehow mysteriously enable it to "spontaneously"
assimilate all the social sciences. Quite the opposite! (Concerning Plekhanov’s
article, see Samuel H. Baron’s Plekhanov [Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 1963], pp.248-253.)]]
The fact that as a science Marxism is an expression of the highest
degree in the development of proletarian class consciousness means simply that
it is only through an individual process of selection that the best, most
experienced, the most intelligent and the most combative members of the
proletariat are able to directly and independently acquire this class
consciousness in its most potent form. To the extent that this acquisition is
an individual one, it also becomes accessible to other social classes and
layers (above all, the revolutionary intelligentsia and the students). [[Today
it is almost forgotten that the Russian socialist movement too was founded
largely by students and intellectuals, and that around three-fourths of a
century ago they were faced with a problem similar to that of the revolutionary
intelligentsia today. Similar, but of course not identical: Today there is an
additional obstacle (the reformist, revisionist mass organisations of the
working class), as well as an additional strength (historical experience,
including the experience of great victory which the revolutionary movement has
accumulated since then).
In What is to Be Done? Lenin speaks explicitly of the
capacity of intellectuals to assimilate "political knowledge," i.e.,
scientific Marxism.]] Any other approach can lead only to an idealisation of
the working class - and ultimately of capitalism itself.
Of course it must always be remembered that Marxism could not
arise independently of the actual development of bourgeois society and of the
class struggle that was inevitably unfolding within it. There is an
inextricable tie between the collective, historical experience of the working
class in struggle and its scientific working out of Marxism as collective,
historical class consciousness in its most potent form. But to maintain that
scientific socialism is an historical product of the proletarian class struggle
is not to say that all or even most members of this class can, with greater or
lesser ease, reproduce this knowledge. Marxism is not an automatic product of
the class struggle and class experience but a result of scientific, theoretical
production. Such an assimilation is made possible only through participation in
that process of production; and this process is by definition an individual
one, even though it is only made possible through the development social forces
of production and class contradictions under capitalism.